[1]
|
Bach, K. (1994) Conversational implicature. Mind and Language, 9, 124-161.
|
[2]
|
Grice, H.P. (1989) Logic and conversation, studies in the way of words. Harvard University Press, Cambridge.
|
[3]
|
Levinson, S.C. (2000) Presumptive meaning: The theory of ge- neralized conversational implicature. MIT Press, Cambridge.
|
[4]
|
Sperber, D. and Wilson, D. (1986) Relevance: Communication and cognition. Harvard University Press, Cambridge, Chapter 4.2-4.4.
|
[5]
|
Bach, K. (1994) Semantic slack. In: Tsohatizidis, S., Ed., Foun- dations of Speech Act Theory, Routledge, London.
|
[6]
|
Bach, K. (2001) Speaking loosely: Sentence nonliterality. In: French, P. and Wettstein, H., Eds., Midwest Studies in Philosophy: Figurative Language, Blackwell Publishers, Hoboken, 249-263.
|
[7]
|
Nicolle, S. and Clark, B. (1999) Experimental pragmatics and what is said: A response to Gibbs and Moise. Cognition, 69, 337-354.
|
[8]
|
Bezuidenhout, A. and Cooper Cutting, J. (2002) Literal meaning, minimal propositions, and pragmatic processing. Journal of Pragmatics, 34, 433-456.
|
[9]
|
Gibbs, R. and Moise, J. (1997) Pragmatics in understanding what is said. Cognition, 62, 51-74.
|
[10]
|
Bezuidenhout, A. and Morris (2004) Implicature, relevance and default pragmatic inference. In: Noeck, I. and Sperber, D., Eds., Experimental Pragmatics, Palgrave Macmillan, Basingstoke.
|
[11]
|
Liu, S., Harnish, R.M. and Garrett, M.F. (2012) Theories and research in experimental pragmatics. 中国社会科学院出版社, 北京.
|